Allmark-Kent 26
roughly define the wild animal story as a scientifically-informed, zoocentric
speculation; a sustained attempt to imagine the lives, experiences, and unique
perspectives of one or more nonhuman protagonists, living independently and
autonomously from humans. Through the study of animal protagonists in the six
twentieth-century texts that I have identified, I will investigate the ways in which
each author engages with this endeavour in a post-Nature Fakers context. It is
worth noting that, at present there are no sustained analyses
of Seton
’s and
Roberts’ influence on subsequent representations of animals in Canadian
literature. Nor has literary studies produced any major investigations
concentrating solely on nonhuman protagonists.
Most established interpretations of the wild animal story undermine
Seton
’s and Roberts’ commitment to representing nonhuman minds and
perspectives, prioritizing anthropocentric readings instead. Even within more
recent literary animal
studies work, efforts to read their work as a sincere
zoocentric endeavour have been minimal. Recalling Bergman’s comments
above, we might attribute this to the general negligence towards real animals,
which seem “almost an embarrassment, a disturbance to the symbolic field”
(Bergman). Here, then, we can begin to detect some factors contributing to the
aura of embarrassment and discomfort attached to the wild animal story. In
literary animal studies, this
is exacerbated by Seton
’s and Roberts’
preoccupation with notions of fact, accuracy, and truth, which drew considerable
attention during the Nature Fakers controversy. Understandably, these claims
are especially problematic for animal-sceptical critics. From the animal-
endorsing perspective of practical zoocriticism, however, I propose that we must
accept some damage to the agency and alterity of the
imagined animal
(its
ability to resist interpretation and representation), if it can be of benefit to the
Allmark-Kent 27
living animal
. Indeed, I have observed that authors of wild animal stories
—both
the original and post-Nature Fakers iterations
—all share a commitment to
seeking some form of practical engagement: raising awareness
of ecological
and conservation issues; encouraging empathy and moral concern for animal
exploitation; facilitating the imaginative exploration of nonhuman perspectives;
or speculating on the upper limits of animal cognitive, social, linguistic,
emotional, or cultural complexity. Hence, in order for such endeavours to be
productive, we must reconcile our embarr
assment with the ‘fantasy of knowing
the animal.’
This issue of ‘knowing’ was much-debated in the Nature Fakers
controversy, but not from an animal-sceptical perspective. In the article that
instigated the debate, “Real
and Sham Natural History,” (1903) John Burroughs
derides Seton’s work by modifying the title to “
Wild Animals I ALONE Have
Known
” (129).
Indeed, Burroughs’ criticism was not that Seton had claimed to
know these animals, but that the abilities and behaviours depicted in the book
were
previous
ly unknown: “There are no stories of animal intelligence and
cunning on record, that I am aware of, that match his” (132). Although the
controversy is remembered in terms of Seton
’s and Roberts’ sentimental
anthropomorphism, it is crucial to observe that these accusations
were made on
the grounds of
Dostları ilə paylaş: